NondetTriples for Nondeterministic Languages

Set Implicit Arguments.
From SLF Require Export LibSepReference.
Close Scope val_scope.
Close Scope trm_scope. (* TODO: scope closed by default *)

Implicit Types f : var.
Implicit Types b : bool.
Implicit Types s : state.
Implicit Types t : trm.
Implicit Types v : val.
Implicit Types n : int.
Implicit Types p : loc.
Implicit Types h : heap.
Implicit Types P : Prop.
Implicit Types H : hprop.
Implicit Types Q : valhprop.

First Pass

In previous chapters, we have considered a quasi-deterministic language; only the addresses of allocated data could vary between two executions of a same term starting in a same state.
In this chapter, we discuss the interpretation of Separation Logic triples in the more general case of non-deterministic languages. To that end, we extend the language with a new primitive operator that produces a random number: the term val_rand n non-deterministically evaluates to an integer between 0 inclusive and n exclusive.
This chapter is organized as follows:
  • Statement of a big-step semantics for non-deterministic languages
  • Proof of reasoning rules for triples
  • Proof of reasoning rules in weakest-precondition style
  • Bonus section: definition of triples for non-deterministic languages with respect to small-step semantics.
For simplicity, we omit from the semantics the treatment of non-recursive functions, which can be encoded using recursive functions; and, likewise, omit the treatment of sequences, which can be encoded using let-bindings.

Non-Deterministic Big-Step Semantics: the Predicate evaln

Previously, we worked with the big-step judgment eval s t s' v, which relates one input state (and term) with one output state (and value). This judgment is well-suited for a deterministic semantics, because one input state leads to at most one result. For a non-deterministic semantics, however, we need to relate one input with a set of possible results.
In Coq, a set of output states can be represented as a set of pairs made of a state and a value, that is, (state*val)->Prop. This type is isomorphic to the type valstateProp, which corresponds exactly to the type of postconditions valhprop. Thus, we are interested in setting up a judgment that relates an "input configuration", described by a state and a term, with a postcondition describing the set of possible "output configurations".
The non-deterministic big-step judgment therefore takes the form evaln s t Q, and relates an input state s and a term t with a postcondition Q. An output configuration consists of an output state s' and an output value v that, together, satisfy the postcondition Q, in the sense that Q v s' holds.
In the context of program verification, we are not so much interested in characterizing exactly the set of all output configurations reachable by the program, but mainly interested in showing that all output configurations satisfy a desired postcondition Q. For this reason, it is perfectly fine for the set of configurations described by Q to over- approximate the set of configurations actually reachable by the program. We'll explain later on how to characterize the set of output configurations in a precise manner.
The judgment evaln s t Q is defined inductively. It asserts that every possible execution starting from configuration (s,t) satisfies the postcondition Q. The definition of evaln is adapted from that of eval. Four cases are particularly interesting.
  • Consider the case of a value. The judgment evaln s t Q asserts that the value v in the state s satisfies the postcondition Q. The premise for deriving that judgment is thus that Q v s must hold.
  • Consider the case of a let-binding. let x = t1 in t2. The first premise of the evaluation rule describes the evaluation of the subterm t1. It takes the form evaln s t1 Q. The second premise describes the evaluation of the the continuation subst x v1 t2 in a state s2, where the value v1 and the state s2 correspond to a configuration that can be produced by t1. In other words, v1 and s2 are assumed to satisfy Q1 v1 s2.
  • Consider the case of a non-deterministic term: val_rand n, evaluated in a state s. The first premise of the rule requires n > 0. The second premise requires that, for any value n1 that val_rand n may evaluate to (that is, such that 0 n1 < n), the configuration made of n1 and s satisfies the postcondition Q, in the sense that Q n1 s holds.
  • Consider the case of an allocation: val_ref v, evaluated in a state s. The premise of the rule asserts that the postcondition Q should hold of any configuration made of a fresh location p and a state s' obtained as the update of s with a binding from p to v.
Inductive evaln : state trm (valstateProp) Prop :=
  | evaln_val : s v Q,
      Q v s
      evaln s (trm_val v) Q
  | evaln_fix : s f x t1 Q,
      Q (val_fix f x t1) s
      evaln s (trm_fix f x t1) Q
  | evaln_app_fix : s v1 v2 f x t1 Q,
      v1 = val_fix f x t1
      evaln s (subst x v2 (subst f v1 t1)) Q
      evaln s (trm_app v1 v2) Q
  | evaln_let : Q1 s x t1 t2 Q,
      evaln s t1 Q1
      ( v1 s2, Q1 v1 s2 evaln s2 (subst x v1 t2) Q)
      evaln s (trm_let x t1 t2) Q
  | evaln_if : s b t1 t2 Q,
      evaln s (if b then t1 else t2) Q
      evaln s (trm_if (val_bool b) t1 t2) Q
  | evaln_add : s n1 n2 Q,
      Q (val_int (n1 + n2)) s
      evaln s (val_add (val_int n1) (val_int n2)) Q
  | evaln_rand : s n Q,
      n > 0
      ( n1, 0 n1 < n Q n1 s)
      evaln s (val_rand (val_int n)) Q
  | evaln_ref : s v Q,
      ( p, ¬ Fmap.indom s p
         Q (val_loc p) (Fmap.update s p v))
      evaln s (val_ref v) Q
  | evaln_get : s p Q,
      Fmap.indom s p
      Q (Fmap.read s p) s
      evaln s (val_get (val_loc p)) Q
  | evaln_set : s p v Q,
      Fmap.indom s p
      Q val_unit (Fmap.update s p v)
      evaln s (val_set (val_loc p) v) Q
  | evaln_free : s p Q,
      Fmap.indom s p
      Q val_unit (Fmap.remove s p)
      evaln s (val_free (val_loc p)) Q.
Observe that evaln s t Q cannot hold if there exists one possible execution of (s,t) that runs into an error, i.e., that reaches a configuration that is stuck. This property reflects on the fact that the judgment evaln asserts that every possible execution terminates safely.
Observe also that evaln is covariant in the postcondition: if evaln s t Q1 holds, and Q2 is weaker than Q1, then evaln s t Q2 also holds. This property reflects on the fact that it is always possible to further over-approximate the set of possible results.
Lemma evaln_conseq : s t Q1 Q2,
  evaln s t Q1
  Q1 ===> Q2
  evaln s t Q2.
Proof using.
  introv M W.
  asserts W': ( v h, Q1 v h Q2 v h). { auto. } clear W.
  induction M; try solve [ constructors* ].
Qed.
The judgment evaln s t Q can interpreted in at least five different ways:
  • The judgment evaln may be viewed as the natural generalization of eval, generalizing from one output to a set of possible output.
  • The judgment evaln may be viewed as an inductive definition of a weakest-precondition judgment. Interestingly, if we swap the order of the arguments to evaln t Q s, then the partial application evaln t Q has type hprop, and its interpretation matches exactly that of a weakest precondition for a Hoare triple. We'll formalize this claim further on in this chapter, and we'll point out shortly afterwards the difference between the rules that define evaln and the traditional weakest-precondition reasoning rules.
  • The judgment evaln may be viewed as a CPS-version of the predicate eval. Indeed, The output of eval, made of an output value and an output state, are "passed on" to the continuation Q.
  • The judgment evaln may be viewed as a particular form of denotational semantics for the language. Each program is interpreted as (i.e., mapped to) a set of mathematical objects, which "simply" consists of pairs of states and "syntactic" values. In particular, functions are interpreted as plain pieces of syntax (not as functions over Scott domains, as usually done).
  • The judgment evaln may be viewed as a generalized form of a typing relation. To make the analogy clear, let us adapt the definition of evaln in two ways, and focus on the evaluation rule for let-bindings. First, let us get rid of the state, i.e., consider a language without side-effects, for simplicity.
         evaln t1 Q1
         ( v1, Q1 v1evaln (subst x v1 t2) Q) →
         evaln (trm_let x t1 t2) Q
    Second, let us switch from a substitution-based semantics to an environment-based semantics---nothing but change of presentation.
         evaln E t1 Q1
         ( v1, Q1 v1evaln ((x,v1)::E) t2 Q) →
         evaln E (trm_let x t1 t2) Q
    Now, let's consider a typing property. For example, expressing that a term has type int amounts to asserting that this term produces a value v of the form val_int n for some n. This property may be captured by the postcondition fun v n, v = val_int n. Let us compare the previous rule with the traditional typing rule shown below.
         typing E t1 Q1
         typing ((x,Q1)::E) t2 Q
         typing E (trm_let x t1 t2) Q
    The only difference is that the evaluation rule maps x to any value v1 such that v1 has type Q1, whereas the typing rule directly maps x to the type Q1. The two presentations are thus essentially equivalent.
In what follows, we discuss the difference between the presentation of the judgment evaln, and the rules that define a weakest precondition. We focus on the particular case of a let-binding.

Exercise: 1 star, standard, optional (evaln_let')

The rule evaln_let shares similarities with the statement of the weakest-precondition style reasoning rule for let-bindings. Prove the following alternative statement, with a wp-style flavor.
Lemma evaln_let' : s1 x t1 t2 Q,
  evaln s1 t1 (fun v1 s2evaln s2 (subst x v1 t2) Q)
  evaln s1 (trm_let x t1 t2) Q.
Proof using. (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.

Exercise: 2 stars, standard, optional (evaln_let_of_evaln_let')

Reciprocally, prove that the statement considered in the inductive definition of evaln is derivable from evaln_let'. More precisely, prove the statement below by using evaln_let' and evaln_conseq.
Lemma evaln_let_of_evaln_let' : Q1 s1 x t1 t2 Q,
  evaln s1 t1 Q1
  ( v1 s2, Q1 v1 s2 evaln s2 (subst x v1 t2) Q)
  evaln s1 (trm_let x t1 t2) Q.
Proof using. (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
One way wonder whether we could have used the wp-style formulation of the semantics of let-bindings directly in the definition of evaln. The answer is negative. Doing so would lead to an invalid inductive definition, involving a "non strictly positive occurrence". To check it out, uncomment the definition below to observe Coq's complaint.
  Inductive evaln' : statetrm → (valstateProp) → Prop :=
    | evaln'_let : Q1 s1 x t1 t2 Q,
       evaln' s1 t1 (fun v1 s2evaln' s2 (subst x v1 t2) Q) →
       evaln' s1 (trm_let x t1 t2) Q.

Interpretation of evaln w.r.t. eval

Given that evaln describes "all possible executions" and that eval describes "one possible execution", there must be formal relationships between the two predicates. These relationships are investigated next.
Recall the big-step evaluation judgment eval. It is the same as before, only extended with evaluation rule for the random number generator, namely eval_rand.
Inductive eval : state trm state val Prop :=
  | eval_val : s v,
      eval s (trm_val v) s v
  | eval_fix : s f x t1,
      eval s (trm_fix f x t1) s (val_fix f x t1)
  | eval_app_fix : s1 s2 v1 v2 f x t1 v,
      v1 = val_fix f x t1
      eval s1 (subst x v2 (subst f v1 t1)) s2 v
      eval s1 (trm_app v1 v2) s2 v
  | eval_let : s1 s2 s3 x t1 t2 v1 r,
      eval s1 t1 s2 v1
      eval s2 (subst x v1 t2) s3 r
      eval s1 (trm_let x t1 t2) s3 r
  | eval_if : s1 s2 b v t1 t2,
      eval s1 (if b then t1 else t2) s2 v
      eval s1 (trm_if (val_bool b) t1 t2) s2 v
  | eval_add : s n1 n2,
      eval s (val_add (val_int n1) (val_int n2)) s (val_int (n1 + n2))
  | eval_rand : s n n1,
      0 n1 < n
      eval s (val_rand (val_int n)) s (val_int n1)
  | eval_ref : s v p,
      ¬ Fmap.indom s p
      eval s (val_ref v) (Fmap.update s p v) (val_loc p)
  | eval_get : s p,
      Fmap.indom s p
      eval s (val_get (val_loc p)) s (Fmap.read s p)
  | eval_set : s p v,
      Fmap.indom s p
      eval s (val_set (val_loc p) v) (Fmap.update s p v) val_unit
  | eval_free : s p,
      Fmap.indom s p
      eval s (val_free (val_loc p)) (Fmap.remove s p) val_unit.
The judgment evaln s t Q asserts that any possible execution of the program (t,s) terminates on an output satisfying the postcondition Q. Thus, if one particular execution terminates on the output (s',v), as described by the judgment eval s t s' v, it must be the case that Q v s' holds. This result is formalized by the following lemma.

Exercise: 3 stars, standard, optional (evaln_inv_eval)

Assume evaln s t Q to hold. Prove that the postcondition Q holds of any output that (s,t) may evaluate to according to the judgment eval.
Lemma evaln_inv_eval : s t v s' Q,
  evaln s t Q
  eval s t s' v
  Q v s'.
Proof using. (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
The judgment evaln s t Q asserts that any possible execution of the program (t,s) terminates on an output satisfying the postcondition Q. This judgment implies, in particular, that there exists at least one such execution, described by a judgment of the form eval s t s' v, where v and s' satisfy the postcondition Q. This second result is formalized by the following lemma.

Exercise: 4 stars, standard, especially useful (evaln_inv_exists_eval)

Assume evaln s t Q to hold. Prove that there exists an output (s',v) that (s,t) may evaluate to according to the judgment eval, and that this output satisfies Q.
Hint: the proof may be carried out either with or without leveraging the lemma evaln_inv_eval, proved above.
Hint: for the case eval_ref, use the following line to assert the existence of a fresh location: forwards* (p&D&N): (exists_fresh null s)..
Lemma evaln_inv_exists_eval : s t Q,
  evaln s t Q
   s' v, eval s t s' v Q v s'.
Proof using. (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
The judgment evaln s t Q associates with a program configuration (s,t) an over-approximation of its possible output configurations, described by Q. For the purpose of defining of Hoare triple, working with over-approximation is perfectly fine. In other contexts, however, it might be interesting to characterize exactly the set of output configurations.
The set of results to which a program (s,t) may evaluate is precisely characterized by the predicate fun v s' eval s t s' v. Let post s t denote exactly that predicate.
Definition post (s:state) (t:trm) : valhprop :=
  fun v s'eval s t s' v.
The judgment evaln s t (post s t) essentially captures the safety of the program (s,t): it asserts that all possible executions terminate without error.
Let us prove that post s t corresponds to the smallest possible post-condition for evaln. In other words, assuming that evaln s t Q holds for some Q, we can prove that evaln s t (post s t) holds, and that the entailment post s t ===> Q holds. This entailment captures the fact that post s t denotes a smaller set of results than Q. Note that evaln s t (post s t) does not hold for a program for which one particular execution may diverge or get stuck.

Exercise: 5 stars, standard, especially useful (evaln_post_of_evaln)

Prove the fact that if evaln s t Q holds for some Q, then it holds for the smallest postcondition, namely post s t. Hint: in the let-binding case, you'll need to either exploit evaln_inv_eval or to provide an explicit intermediate postcondition for the subterm t1 that revers to Q1.
Lemma evaln_post_of_evaln : s t Q,
  evaln s t Q
  evaln s t (post s t).
Proof using. (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.

Exercise: 2 stars, standard, especially useful (evaln_inv_post_qimpl)

Prove the fact that if evaln s t Q holds, then post s t ===> Q, i.e. the smallest-possible postcondition entails the postcondition Q. Hint: the proof is only one line long.
Lemma evaln_inv_post_qimpl : s t Q,
  evaln s t Q
  post s t ===> Q.
Proof using. (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.

Triples for Non-Deterministic Big-Step Semantics

A Hoare triple, written hoaren t H Q, asserts that, for any input state s satisfying the precondition H, all executions of t in that state s terminate and produce an output satisfying the postcondition Q.
Definition hoaren (t:trm) (H:hprop) (Q:valhprop) : Prop :=
   (s:state), H s evaln s t Q.
In prior chapters, we defined a Separation Logic triple, written triplen t H Q, by quantifying over the "rest of the word". Concretely, we used the definition (H':hprop), hoare t (H \* H') (Q \*+ H'). Doing so was necessary because the definition we had for hoare did not satisfy the frame rule.
It turns out that hoaren does satisfy the frame rule. Thus, we can define Separation Logic triples directly as the predicate hoaren.
Definition triplen (t:trm) (H:hprop) (Q:valhprop) : Prop :=
   (s:state), H s evaln s t Q.
The most important step of the proof is to argue that evaln is stable by extension with a disjoint piece of heap. This proof is by induction. The most (and only) interesting step is that of allocation. In a derivation built using evaln_ref, we are given an assumption about all locations p fresh from h1. What we are trying to build is a fact mentioning all locations p fresh from h1 \u h2. We are thus restricting the set of p that can be considered for allocation, hence the result holds.
Lemma evaln_frame : h1 h2 t Q,
  evaln h1 t Q
  Fmap.disjoint h1 h2
  evaln (h1 \u h2) t (Q \*+ (= h2)).
Proof using.
  introv M HD. gen h2. induction M; intros;
    try solve [ hint hstar_intro; constructors* ].
  { rename M into M1, H into M2, IHM into IH1, H0 into IH2.
    specializes IH1 HD. applys evaln_let IH1. introv HK.
    lets (h1'&h2'&K1'&K2'&KD&KU): hstar_inv HK. subst. applys* IH2. }
  { rename H into M. applys evaln_ref. intros p Hp.
    rewrite Fmap.indom_union_eq in Hp. rew_logic in Hp. destruct Hp as [Hp1 Hp2].
    rewrite* Fmap.update_union_not_r. applys hstar_intro.
    { applys* M. } { auto. } { applys* Fmap.disjoint_update_not_r. } }
  { applys evaln_get. { rewrite* Fmap.indom_union_eq. }
    { rewrite* Fmap.read_union_l. applys* hstar_intro. } }
  { applys evaln_set. { rewrite* Fmap.indom_union_eq. }
    { rewrite* Fmap.update_union_l. applys hstar_intro.
      { auto. } { auto. } { applys* Fmap.disjoint_update_l. } } }
  { applys evaln_free. { rewrite* Fmap.indom_union_eq. }
    { rewrite* Fmap.remove_disjoint_union_l. applys hstar_intro.
      { auto. } { auto. } { applys* Fmap.disjoint_remove_l. } } }
Qed.
From evaln_frame, we can derive the standard frame rule for triplen.
Lemma triplen_frame : t H Q H',
  triplen t H Q
  triplen t (H \* H') (Q \*+ H').
Proof.
  introv M. intros h HF. lets (h1&h2&M1&M2&MD&MU): hstar_inv (rm HF).
  subst. specializes M M1. applys evaln_conseq.
  { applys evaln_frame M MD. } { xsimpl. intros h' →. applys M2. }
Qed.
Other structural rules
Lemma triplen_conseq : t H' Q' H Q,
  triplen t H' Q'
  H ==> H'
  Q' ===> Q
  triplen t H Q.
Proof using.
  unfolds triplen. introv M MH MQ HF. applys* evaln_conseq.
Qed.

Lemma triplen_hexists : t (A:Type) (J:Ahprop) Q,
  ( x, triplen t (J x) Q)
  triplen t (hexists J) Q.
Proof using. introv M. intros h (x&Hh). applys M Hh. Qed.

Lemma triplen_hpure : t (P:Prop) H Q,
  (P triplen t H Q)
  triplen t (\[P] \* H) Q.
Proof using.
  introv M. intros h (h1&h2&M1&M2&D&U). destruct M1 as (M1&HP).
  lets E: hempty_inv HP. subst. rewrite Fmap.union_empty_l. applys¬M.
Qed.
Rules for term constructs
Lemma triplen_val : v H Q,
  H ==> Q v
  triplen (trm_val v) H Q.
Proof using. introv M. intros h K. applys* evaln_val. Qed.

Lemma triplen_fix : f x t1 H Q,
  H ==> Q (val_fix f x t1)
  triplen (trm_fix f x t1) H Q.
Proof using. introv M. intros h K. applys* evaln_fix. Qed.

Lemma triplen_app_fix : v1 v2 f x t1 H Q,
  v1 = val_fix f x t1
  triplen (subst x v2 (subst f v1 t1)) H Q
  triplen (trm_app v1 v2) H Q.
Proof using. introv E M. intros h K. applys* evaln_app_fix. Qed.

Lemma triplen_let : x t1 t2 H Q Q1,
  triplen t1 H Q1
  ( v1, triplen (subst x v1 t2) (Q1 v1) Q)
  triplen (trm_let x t1 t2) H Q.
Proof using. introv M1 M2. intros h K. applys* evaln_let. Qed.

Lemma triplen_if : (b:bool) t1 t2 H Q,
  triplen (if b then t1 else t2) H Q
  triplen (trm_if b t1 t2) H Q.
Proof using. introv M. intros h K. applys* evaln_if. Qed.
Rules for primitive operations
Lemma triplen_add : H n1 n2,
  triplen (val_add n1 n2)
    H
    (fun r\[r = val_int (n1 + n2)] \* H).
Proof using.
  intros. intros h K. applys* evaln_add. rewrite* hstar_hpure_l.
Qed.

Lemma triplen_rand : n,
  n > 0
  triplen (val_rand n)
    \[]
    (fun r\ n1, \[0 n1 < n] \* \[r = val_int n1]).
Proof using.
  introv N. intros h K. applys* evaln_rand.
  lets ->: hempty_inv K.
  intros n1 H1. applys* hexists_intro n1. rewrite* hstar_hpure_l.
  split*. applys* hpure_intro.
Qed.

Lemma triplen_ref : H v,
  triplen (val_ref v)
    H
    (fun r(\ p, \[r = val_loc p] \* p ~~> v) \* H).
Proof using.
  intros. intros s1 K. applys evaln_ref. intros p D.
  unfolds update. applys hstar_intro K.
  { applys hexists_intro p. rewrite hstar_hpure_l.
    split*. applys hsingle_intro. }
  { applys* disjoint_single_of_not_indom. }
Qed.

Lemma triplen_get : H v p,
  triplen (val_get p)
    ((p ~~> v) \* H)
    (fun r\[r = v] \* (p ~~> v) \* H).
Proof using.
  intros. intros s K.
  lets (h1&h2&P1&P2&D&->): hstar_inv (rm K).
  lets E1: hsingle_inv P1. lets I1: indom_single p v.
  applys evaln_get.
  { applys* Fmap.indom_union_l. subst. applys indom_single. }
  { rewrite hstar_hpure_l. split.
    { subst h1. rewrite* Fmap.read_union_l. rewrite* Fmap.read_single. }
    { applys* hstar_intro. } }
Qed.

Lemma triplen_set : H w p v,
  triplen (val_set (val_loc p) v)
    ((p ~~> w) \* H)
    (fun r\[r = val_unit] \* (p ~~> v) \* H).
Proof using.
  intros. intros s1 K.
  lets (h1&h2&P1&P2&D&->): hstar_inv (rm K).
  lets E1: hsingle_inv P1. lets I1: indom_single p v.
  applys evaln_set.
  { applys* Fmap.indom_union_l. subst. applys indom_single. }
  { rewrite hstar_hpure_l. split*.
    { subst h1. rewrite* Fmap.update_union_l. rewrite* update_single.
      applys hstar_intro.
      { applys* hsingle_intro. }
      { auto. }
      { applys Fmap.disjoint_single_set D. }
      { auto. applys indom_single. } } }
Qed.

Lemma triplen_free : H p v,
  triplen (val_free (val_loc p))
    ((p ~~> v) \* H)
    (fun r\[r = val_unit] \* H).
Proof using.
  intros. intros s1 K.
  lets (h1&h2&P1&P2&D&->): hstar_inv (rm K).
  lets E1: hsingle_inv P1. lets I1: indom_single p v.
  applys evaln_free.
  { applys* Fmap.indom_union_l. subst. applys indom_single. }
  { rewrite hstar_hpure_l. split*.
    { subst h1. rewrite* Fmap.remove_union_single_l.
      { intros Dl. applys* Fmap.disjoint_inv_not_indom_both D Dl. } } }
Qed.

More Details

Weakest-Precondition Style Presentation.

In chapter WPsem, we discussed several possible definitions of the weakest-precondition operator, namely wp, in Separation Logic. In this chapter, we present yet another possible definition, based on the judgment evaln.
Consider the judgment evaln s t Q. Assume the arguments were reordered, yielding the judgment evaln t Q s. Consider now the partial application evaln t Q. This partial application has type stateProp, that is, hprop. This predicate evaln t Q denotes a predicate that characterizes the set of input states s in which the evaluation (or, rather, any possible evaluation) of the term t produces an output satisfying Q. It thus corresponds exactly to the notion of weakest precondition for Hoare Logic.
The judgment hoarewpns t Q, defined below, simply reorder the arguments of evaln so as to produce this weakest-precondition operator. Note that this is a Hoare Logic style predicate, which talks about the full state.
Definition wpn (t:trm) (Q:valhprop) : hprop :=
  fun sevaln s t Q.
We can check the standard equivalence (H ==> wp t Q) (triple t H Q), for the predicates wpn and triplen.
Lemma wpn_equiv : H t Q,
  (H ==> wpn t Q) (triplen t H Q).
Proof using. unfolds triplen, wpn. iff M; autos*. Qed.
Remark: as mentioned in the chapter WPsem, it is possible to define the predicate triplen t H Q as H ==> wpn t Q, that is, to define triplen as a notion derived from wpn and wpn.

WP-Style Rules for a Non-Deterministic Semantics.

Given that the semantics expressed by the predicate evaln has a weakest- precondition flavor, there are good chances that deriving weakest- precondition style reasoning rules from evaln could be even easier than deriving the rules for triplen. Thus, let us investigate whether this is indeed the case, by stating and proving reasoning rules for the judgment wpn.
Structural rules
Lemma wpn_frame : t H Q,
  (wpn t Q) \* H ==> wpn t (Q \*+ H).
Proof using.
  intros. unfold wpn. intros h HF.
  lets (h1&h2&M1&M2&MD&MU): hstar_inv (rm HF).
  subst. applys evaln_conseq.
  { applys evaln_frame M1 MD. }
  { xsimpl. intros h' →. applys M2. }
Qed.

Lemma wpn_conseq : t Q1 Q2,
  Q1 ===> Q2
  (wpn t Q1) ==> (wpn t Q2).
Proof using.
  introv W. unfold wpn. intros h K. applys evaln_conseq K W.
Qed.
Derived structural rules
Lemma wpn_ramified : t Q1 Q2,
  (wpn t Q1) \* (Q1 \−−∗ Q2) ==> (wpn t Q2).
Proof using.
  intros. applys himpl_trans.
  { applys wpn_frame. }
  { applys wpn_conseq. xsimpl. }
Qed.

Lemma wpn_conseq_frame : t H Q1 Q2,
  Q1 \*+ H ===> Q2
  (wpn t Q1) \* H ==> (wpn t Q2).
Proof using.
  introv M. rewrite <- qwand_equiv in M. xchange M. applys wpn_ramified.
Qed.

Lemma wpn_ramified_trans : t H Q1 Q2,
  H ==> (wpn t Q1) \* (Q1 \−−∗ Q2)
  H ==> (wpn t Q2).
Proof using. introv M. xchange M. applys wpn_ramified. Qed.
Rules for term constructs
Lemma wpn_val : v Q,
  Q v ==> wpn (trm_val v) Q.
Proof using.
  unfold wpn. intros. intros h K. applys* evaln_val.
Qed.

Lemma wpn_fix : f x t Q,
  Q (val_fix f x t) ==> wpn (trm_fix f x t) Q.
Proof using.
  unfold wpn. intros. intros h K. applys* evaln_fix.
Qed.

Lemma wpn_app_fix : f x v1 v2 t1 Q,
  v1 = val_fix f x t1
  wpn (subst x v2 (subst f v1 t1)) Q ==> wpn (trm_app v1 v2) Q.
Proof using.
  unfold wpn. intros. intros h K. applys* evaln_app_fix.
Qed.

Lemma wpn_let : x t1 t2 Q,
      wpn t1 (fun vwpn (subst x v t2) Q)
  ==> wpn (trm_let x t1 t2) Q.
Proof using.
  unfold wpn. intros. intros h K. applys* evaln_let.
Qed.

Lemma wpn_if : b t1 t2 Q,
  wpn (if b then t1 else t2) Q ==> wpn (trm_if b t1 t2) Q.
Proof using.
  unfold wpn. intros. intros h K. applys* evaln_if.
Qed.
Rules for primitives. We state their specifications following the presentation described near the end of chapter Wand.
Lemma wpn_add : Q n1 n2,
  (Q (val_int (n1 + n2))) ==> wpn (val_add (val_int n1) (val_int n2)) Q.
Proof using.
  unfolds wpn. intros. intros h K. applys* evaln_add.
Qed.

Lemma wpn_rand : Q n,
  n > 0
      (\ n1, \[0 n1 < n] \−∗ Q (val_int n1))
  ==> wpn (val_rand (val_int n)) Q.
Proof using.
  unfolds wpn. introv N. xsimpl. intros h K.
  applys* evaln_rand. intros n1 H1. lets K': hforall_inv K n1.
  rewrite* hwand_hpure_l in K'.
Qed.

Lemma wpn_ref : Q v,
  (\ p, (p ~~> v) \−∗ Q (val_loc p)) ==> wpn (val_ref v) Q.
Proof using.
  unfolds wpn. intros. intros h K. applys* evaln_ref. intros p D.
  lets K': hforall_inv (rm K) p.
  applys hwand_inv (single p v) K'.
  { applys hsingle_intro. }
  { applys* disjoint_single_of_not_indom. }
Qed.

Lemma wpn_get : v p Q,
  (p ~~> v) \* (p ~~> v \−∗ Q v) ==> wpn (val_get p) Q.
Proof using.
  unfolds wpn. intros. intros h K.
  lets (h1&h2&P1&P2&D&->): hstar_inv (rm K).
  forwards*: hwand_inv h1 P2.
  lets E1: hsingle_inv P1. lets I1: indom_single p v.
  applys evaln_get.
  { applys* Fmap.indom_union_l. subst. applys indom_single. }
  { subst h1. rewrite* Fmap.read_union_l. rewrite* Fmap.read_single. }
Qed.

Lemma wpn_set : v w p Q,
  (p ~~> v) \* (p ~~> w \−∗ Q val_unit) ==> wpn (val_set p w) Q.
Proof using.
  unfolds wpn. intros. intros h K.
  lets (h1&h2&P1&P2&D&->): hstar_inv (rm K).
  lets E1: hsingle_inv P1. lets I1: indom_single p v.
  forwards: hwand_inv (single p w) P2.
  { applys hsingle_intro. }
  { subst h1. applys Fmap.disjoint_single_set D. }
    { applys evaln_set.
    { applys* Fmap.indom_union_l. subst. applys indom_single. }
    { subst h1. rewrite* Fmap.update_union_l. rewrite* update_single. } }
Qed.

Lemma wpn_free : v p Q,
  (p ~~> v) \* (Q val_unit) ==> wpn (val_free p) Q.
Proof using.
  unfolds wpn. intros. intros h K.
  lets (h1&h2&P1&P2&D&->): hstar_inv (rm K).
  lets E1: hsingle_inv P1. lets I1: indom_single p v.
  applys_eq evaln_free.
  { applys* Fmap.indom_union_l. subst. applys indom_single. }
  { subst h1. rewrite¬Fmap.remove_union_single_l.
    intros Dl. applys* Fmap.disjoint_inv_not_indom_both D Dl. }
Qed.
Rules for primitives, alternative presentation using triples.
Lemma triplen_add' : n1 n2,
  triplen (val_add n1 n2)
    \[]
    (fun r\[r = val_int (n1 + n2)]).
Proof using.
  intros. rewrite <- wpn_equiv.
  applys himpl_trans; [| applys wpn_add ]. xsimpl*.
Qed.

Lemma triplen_rand' : n,
  n > 0
  triplen (val_rand n)
    \[]
    (fun r\ n1, \[0 n1 < n] \* \[r = val_int n1]).
Proof using.
  introv N. rewrite <- wpn_equiv.
  applys himpl_trans; [| applys* wpn_rand ]. xsimpl*.
Qed.

Lemma triplen_ref' : v,
  triplen (val_ref v)
    \[]
    (fun r\ p, \[r = val_loc p] \* p ~~> v).
Proof using.
  intros. rewrite <- wpn_equiv.
  applys himpl_trans; [| applys wpn_ref ]. xsimpl*.
Qed.

Lemma triplen_get' : v p,
  triplen (val_get p)
    (p ~~> v)
    (fun r\[r = v] \* (p ~~> v)).
Proof using.
  intros. rewrite <- wpn_equiv.
  applys himpl_trans; [| applys wpn_get ]. xsimpl*.
Qed.

Lemma triplen_set' : w p v,
  triplen (val_set (val_loc p) v)
    (p ~~> w)
    (fun _p ~~> v).
Proof using.
  intros. rewrite <- wpn_equiv.
  applys himpl_trans; [| applys wpn_set ]. xsimpl*.
Qed.

Lemma triplen_free' : p v,
  triplen (val_free (val_loc p))
    (p ~~> v)
    (fun _\[]).
Proof using.
  intros. rewrite <- wpn_equiv.
  applys himpl_trans; [| applys wpn_free ]. xsimpl*.
Qed.

Exercise: 4 stars, standard, optional (wpn_rand_of_triplen_rand)

The proof of lemma triplen_rand shows that a triple-based specification of val_rand is derivable from a wp-style specification. In this exercise, we aim to prove the reciprocal. Concretely, prove the following specification by exploiting triplen_rand. Hint: make use of wpn_equiv.
Lemma wpn_rand_of_triplen_rand : n Q,
  n > 0
      (\ n1, \[0 n1 < n] \−∗ Q (val_int n1))
  ==> wpn (val_rand (val_int n)) Q.
Proof using. (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.

Optional Material

So far, this chapter has focused on handling non-determinism in the context of using a big-step semantics. In this bonus section, we investigate the treatment of non-determinism using a small-step semantics. Moreover, we establish equivalence proofs relating (non-deterministic) small-step and big-step semantics.

Interpretation of evaln w.r.t. eval and terminates

The predicate terminates s t asserts that all executions of the configuration t/s terminate---none of them diverges or get stuck. Its definition is a simplified version of evaln where all occurences of Q are removed. In the rule for let-bindings, namely terminates_let, the quantification over the configuration v1/s2 is done by refering to the big-step judgment eval.
Inductive terminates : state trm Prop :=
  | terminates_val : s v,
      terminates s (trm_val v)
  | terminates_fix : s f x t1,
      terminates s (trm_fix f x t1)
  | terminates_app_fix : s v1 v2 f x t1,
      v1 = val_fix f x t1
      terminates s (subst x v2 (subst f v1 t1))
      terminates s (trm_app v1 v2)
  | terminates_let : s x t1 t2,
      terminates s t1
      ( v1 s2, eval s t1 s2 v1 terminates s2 (subst x v1 t2))
      terminates s (trm_let x t1 t2)
  | terminates_if : s b t1 t2,
      terminates s (if b then t1 else t2)
      terminates s (trm_if (val_bool b) t1 t2)
  | terminates_add : s n1 n2,
      terminates s (val_add (val_int n1) (val_int n2))
  | terminates_rand : s n,
      n > 0
      terminates s (val_rand (val_int n))
  | terminates_ref : s v,
      terminates s (val_ref v)
  | terminates_get : s p,
      Fmap.indom s p
      terminates s (val_get (val_loc p))
  | terminates_set : s p v,
      Fmap.indom s p
      terminates s (val_set (val_loc p) v)
  | terminates_free : s p,
      Fmap.indom s p
      terminates s (val_free (val_loc p)).

Section EvalnTerminates.
Hint Constructors eval evaln.

Exercise: 5 stars, standard, especially useful (evaln_iff_terminates_and_post)

Prove that evaln s t Q is equivalent to the conjunction of terminates s t and to a partial correctness result asserting that if an evaluation of t/s terminates on some result then this result satisfies Q.
Lemma evaln_iff_terminates_and_post : s t Q,
  evaln s t Q (terminates s t ( v s', eval s t s' v Q v s')).
Proof using. (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Let Any denotes the postcondition that accepts any result.
Definition Any : valstateProp :=
  fun v sTrue.

Hint Unfold Any.

Exercise: 2 stars, standard, especially useful (terminates_iff_evaln_any)

Prove that terminates s t is equivalent to evaln s t Any. Hint: exploit evaln_iff_terminates_and_post.
Lemma terminates_iff_evaln_any : s t,
  terminates s t evaln s t Any.
Proof using. (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.

Small-Step Evaluation Relation

The judgment step s t s' t' describes the small-step reduction relation: it asserts that the program configuration (s,t) can take one reduction step towards the program configuration (s',t'). Its definition, shown below, is standard.
Inductive step : state trm state trm Prop :=

  (* Unique context rule *)
  | step_let_ctx : s1 s2 x t1 t1' t2,
      step s1 t1 s2 t1'
      step s1 (trm_let x t1 t2) s2 (trm_let x t1' t2)

  (* Beta reductions *)
  | step_fix : s f x t1,
      step s (trm_fix f x t1) s (val_fix f x t1)
  | step_app_fix : s v1 v2 f x t1,
      v1 = val_fix f x t1
      step s (trm_app v1 v2) s (subst x v2 (subst f v1 t1))
  | step_if : s b t1 t2,
      step s (trm_if (val_bool b) t1 t2) s (if b then t1 else t2)
  | step_let : s x t2 v1,
      step s (trm_let x v1 t2) s (subst x v1 t2)

  (* Primitive operations *)
  | step_add : s n1 n2,
      step s (val_add (val_int n1) (val_int n2)) s (val_int (n1 + n2))
  | step_rand : s n n1,
      0 n1 < n
      step s (val_rand (val_int n)) s (val_int n1)
  | step_ref : s v p,
      ¬ Fmap.indom s p
      step s (val_ref v) (Fmap.update s p v) (val_loc p)
  | step_get : s p,
      Fmap.indom s p
      step s (val_get (val_loc p)) s (Fmap.read s p)
  | step_set : s p v,
      Fmap.indom s p
      step s (val_set (val_loc p) v) (Fmap.update s p v) val_unit
  | step_free : s p,
      Fmap.indom s p
      step s (val_free (val_loc p)) (Fmap.remove s p) val_unit.
Consider a configuration (s,t), where t is not a value. If this configuration cannot take any reduction step, it is said to be "stuck".
The judgment evals s t s' t' corresponds to the reflexive-transitive closure of step. Concretely, this judgment asserts that the configuration (s,t) can reduce in zero, one, or several evals to (s',t').
Inductive evals : state trm state trm Prop :=
  | evals_refl : s t,
      evals s t s t
  | evals_step : s1 s2 s3 t1 t2 t3,
      step s1 t1 s2 t2
      evals s2 t2 s3 t3
      evals s1 t1 s3 t3.

Small-Step Characterization of evalns: Attempts

For a non-determinstic language, evals s t s' t' asserts that there exists one possible evaluation from (s,t) to (s',t'). This judgment says nothing about all other possible evaluations.
On the contrary, the predicate evaln s t Q, introduced earlier in this chapter, says something about all possible evaluations. More precisely, evaln s t Q asserts that all possible evaluations of (s,t) reach a final configuration satisfying the postcondition Q.
We are thus interested in defining a judgment of the form evalns s t Q, that is logically equivalent to evaln s t Q, but whose definition is based on the small-step semantics.
In the particular case of a deterministic semantics, we could define evalns s t Q in terms of the transitive evaluation relation evals as follows.
Definition evalns_attempt_1 (s:state) (t:trm) (Q:valhprop) : Prop :=
   v s', evals s t s' (trm_val v) Q v s'.
Quiz: Before reading further, try to devise a definition of evalns s t Q expressed in terms for the judgment evals that applies to the general case of non-deterministic semantics.
Let's check out several candidate definitions for the judgment evalns.
The definition evalns_attempt_2 s t Q asserts that any execution starting from configuration (s,t) and ending on a final configuration (s',v) is such that the final configuration satisfies the postcondition Q. Yet, this definition fails to rule out the possibility of executions that get stuck. Thus, it is only applicable for semantics that include error-propagation rules, and for which there are no stuck terms.
Definition evalns_attempt_2 (s:state) (t:trm) (Q:valhprop) : Prop :=
   v s', evals s t s' (trm_val v) Q v s'.
The definition evalns_attempt_3 s t Q asserts that any execution starting from configuration (s,t) and reaching a state (s',t') is such that either t' is a value v and (s',v) satisfies the postcondition Q, or (s',t') can take a step. Yet, this definition fails to capture the fact that all execution of t should terminate. Thus, it is only useful for capturing partial correctness properties.
Definition evalns_attempt_3 (s:state) (t:trm) (Q:valhprop) : Prop :=
   s2 t2, evals s t s2 t2
       ( v2, t2 = trm_val v2 Q v2 s2)
     ( s3 t3, step s2 t2 s3 t3).
The definition evalns_attempt_4 s t Q asserts that every execution prefix starting from (s,t) may be completed into an execution that does terminate on a configuration that satisfies the postcondition Q.
Definition evalns_attempt_4 (s:state) (t:trm) (Q:valhprop) : Prop :=
   s2 t2, evals s t s2 t2
   v3 s3, evals s2 t2 s3 (trm_val v3) Q v3 s3.
Quiz: Why is evalns_attempt_4 not equivalent to evaln? Can you find a counter-example program for which the property "all possible evaluations reach a final configuration satisfying the postcondition" does not hold?
Solution follows.
Consider the following program, which does satisfy evalns_attempt_4 yet whose execution may diverge.
     let rec f () =
       if (val_rand 2) = 0 then () else f ()
Consider an execution that has already performed a number of recursive calls. This execution may terminate in a finite number of evaluation evals. Indeed, the next call to val_rand may return zero. However, not all executions terminate. Indeed, the execution path where all calls to val_rand return 1, the program runs forever.
The key challenge is to capture the property that "every possible execution terminates". To that end, let's consider yet another approach, based on the idea of bounding the number of execution steps.
The judgment nbevals n s t s' t', defined below, asserts that the configuration (s,t) may reduce in exactly n steps to (s',t'). Its definition follows that of the judgment evals, only with an extra argument for counting the number of steps.
Inductive nbevals : nat state trm state trm Prop :=
  | nbevals_refl : s t,
      nbevals 0 s t s t
  | nbevals_step : (n:nat) s1 s2 s3 t1 t2 t3,
      step s1 t1 s2 t2
      nbevals n s2 t2 s3 t3
      nbevals (S n) s1 t1 s3 t3.
Using the judgment nbevals, we are able to bound the length of all executions. The judgment steps_at_most nmax s t, defined below, asserts that there does not exist any execution starting from (s,t) that exceeds nmax reduction steps.
Definition steps_at_most (nmax:nat) (s:state) (t:trm) : Prop :=
   (n:nat) s2 t2, n > nmax ¬ (nbevals n s t s2 t2).
The judgment evalns_attempt_5 s t Q corresponds to the conjunction of the judgment evalns_attempt_3 s t Q, which asserts partial correctness, and of the judgment nmax, steps_at_most nmax s t, which asserts that there exists an upper bound to the length of all possible executions.
Definition evalns_attempt_5 (s:state) (t:trm) (Q:valhprop) : Prop :=
     (evalns_attempt_3 s t Q)
   ( nmax, steps_at_most nmax s t).
Is the definition of evalns_attempt_5 satisfying? Not quite. First, this definition is fairly complex, and not so easy to work with. Second, and perhaps most importantly, this definition does not apply to all programming languages. It applies only to semantics for which each configuration admits at most a finite number of possible transitions.
If we view the possible executions of a program as a tree, with each branch corresponding to a possible execution, then definition evalns_attempt_5 only properly captures the notion of total correctness for "finitely branching trees", in which every node has a finite number of branches.
Concretely, the definition evalns_attempt_5 would rule out legitimate programs in a language that includes an "unbounded" sources of non- determinism. For example, consider a random number generator that applies to the unit argument and may return any integer value in Z. Such an operator could be formalized as follows.
Parameter val_unbounded_rand : val.

Parameter evaln_unbounded_rand : s Q,
  ( n1, Q n1 s)
  evaln s (val_unbounded_rand val_unit) Q.
Quiz: devise a counter-example program such that (1) every possible execution of this program does terminate, and (2) this program does not satisfy evalns_attempt_5 because there does not exist an upper bound on the length of all executions.
Solution: Consider the following program.
     let rec f n =
       if n > 0 then f (n-1) else () in
     f (unbounded_rand())
The number of execution evals can be arbitrary. Yet, any given program execution terminates.
Arguably, a stand-alone piece of hardware does not feature such "unbounded" source of non-determinism, because each transition at the hardware level involves the manipulation of at most a finite number of bits. However, as soon as I/O is involved, unbounded non-determinism may arise. For example, a language that features an input_string method allowing the user to input strings of arbitrary size is a language with a source of unbounded non-determinism.
Remark: the fact that evalns_attempt_5 only properly captures total correctness for finitely branching trees is related to a result known as König's lemma. This result from graph theory, in the particular case of trees, asserts that "every infinite tree contains either a vertex of infinite degree or an infinite path", or equivalently, asserts that "a finitely branching tree is infinite iff it has an infinite path".
The contraposed statement asserts that a finitely branching tree (corresponding to executions in a language with bounded determinism) is finite (i.e., admits a bound on the depth) iff it has no infinite path (i.e., if all executions terminate).
In summary:
  • evalns_attempt_1 applies only to deterministic semantics.
  • evalns_attempt_2 applies only to complete semantics, i.e., semantics without stuck terms.
  • evalns_attempt_3 captures partial correctness only, and says nothing about termination.
  • evalns_attempt_4 also fails to properly capture termination.
  • evalns_attempt_5 captures total correctness only for semantics that feature only bounded sources of non-determinism, i.e., with a finite number of possible transitions from each configuration.
Our attempts to define a judgment evalns s t Q in terms of evals or in terms of its depth-indexed variant nbevals have failed. It thus appears necessary to search instead for a definition of evalns expressed directly in terms of the one-step reduction relation step.

Small-Step Characterization of evaln: A Solution

In what follows, we present an inductive definition for evalns s t Q. To begin with, let us consider the particular case of a deterministic language.
The predicate evalds s t Q asserts that the (deterministic) evaluation starting from configuration (s,t) produces an output satisfying the predicate Q. It is defined inductively as follows.
  • Base case: evalds s v Q holds if the postcondition holds of this current state, that is, Q v s holds.
  • Step case: evalds s t Q holds if (s,t) one-step reduces to the configuration (s',t') and evalds s' t' Q holds.
Inductive evalds : statetrm->(valhprop)->Prop :=
  | evalds_val : s v Q,
      Q v s
      evalds s v Q
  | evalds_step : s t s' t' Q,
      step s t s' t'
      evalds s' t' Q
      evalds s t Q.
Let us now generalize the inductive definition of evalds to the general case of non-deterministic semantics.
  • Base case: it does not change, that is, evalns s v Q requires Q s v.
  • Step case: this case needs to be refined to account for all possible evaluations, and not just the unique possible evaluation. There are two requirements. First, evalns s t Q requires that the configuration (s,t) is not stuck, that is, it requires the existence of at least one possible reduction step. Second, evalns s t Q requires that, for any configuration (s',t') that (s,t) might reduce to, the property evalns s' t' Q holds.
The definition of evalns may thus be formalized as shown below.
Inductive evalns : statetrm->(valhprop)->Prop :=
  | evalns_val : s v Q,
      Q v s
      evalns s v Q
  | evalns_step : s t Q,
      ( s' t', step s t s' t')
      ( s' t', step s t s' t' evalns s' t' Q)
      evalns s t Q.
Observe how this definition allows for evalns s t Q to hold even for the program such as the counter-example considered for definition evalns_attempt_5, i.e., the program that performs unbounded_rand() recursive calls. The judgment evalns holds for this program, although there exists no bound on the depth of the corresponding derivation. This possibility stems from the fact that the s' t' quantification in constructor evalns_step introduces an infinite branching factor in the derivation tree, for a language that includes the primitive operation unbounded_rand.

Exercise: 2 stars, standard, optional (evalns_val_inv)

Prove the following inversion lemma, which asserts that evalns s v Q implies Q s v.
Lemma evalns_val_inv : s v Q,
  evalns s v Q
  Q v s.
Proof using. (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
In the remaining of this chapter, we present:
  • a definition of Separation Logic triples based on evalns; the corresponding judgment is named triplens
  • the proof of the reasoning rules associated with triplens;
  • a formal proof of equivalence between evalns and evaln, relating the small-step-based definition to the big-step-based definition introduced in the first part of this chapter.

Reasoning Rules for evalns

Reasoning rules have a big-step flavor, thus to derive them we first need to derive big-step style reasoning rules for evalns.
Again, the key step is to argue for the frame property, first for evalns, then for triplens.
Section EvalnsProperties.
Hint Constructors step.

Lemma evalns_frame : h1 h2 t Q,
  evalns h1 t Q
  Fmap.disjoint h1 h2
  evalns (h1 \u h2) t (Q \*+ (= h2)).
Proof using.
  introv M HD. gen h2. induction M; intros.
  { applys evalns_val. applys* hstar_intro. }
  { rename H into M1, H0 into M2, H1 into IH2.
    applys evalns_step.
    { clear M2 IH2. destruct M1 as (s'&t'&R).
      induction R; tryfalse; try solve [ do 2 esplit; constructors* ].
      { forwards* (s'&t'&R'): IHR. }
      { lets (p'&F&_): exists_fresh null (Fmap.union s h2). do 2 esplit.
        applys step_ref v p'. eauto. }
      { do 2 esplit. applys step_get. applys* Fmap.indom_union_l. }
      { do 2 esplit. applys step_set. applys* Fmap.indom_union_l. }
      { do 2 esplit. applys step_free. applys* Fmap.indom_union_l. } }
    { introv R. cuts (s1'&E'&D'&R'):
       ( s1', s' = s1' \u h2 Fmap.disjoint s1' h2 step s t s1' t').
      { subst. applys* IH2. }
      clear M2 IH2.
      gen_eq su: (s \u h2). gen s.
      induction R; intros; subst; eauto.
      { destruct M1 as (s0&t0&R0). (* inverts R0; tryfalse. *)
        rename R into R1. forwards* (s1'&E&D&R1'): IHR s.
        inverts R0. { eauto. } { inverts R1. } }
      { rename H into D. rewrite Fmap.indom_union_eq in D. rew_logic in D.
        destruct D as (D1&D2). esplit. splits.
        { rewrite* Fmap.update_union_not_r. }
        { applys* Fmap.disjoint_update_not_r. }
        { eauto. } }
      { destruct M1 as (se&te&Re). inverts Re; tryfalse.
        rewrite* Fmap.read_union_l. }
      { destruct M1 as (se&te&Re). inverts Re; tryfalse. esplit. splits.
        { rewrite* Fmap.update_union_l. }
        { applys* Fmap.disjoint_update_l. }
        { eauto. } }
      { destruct M1 as (se&te&Re). inverts Re; tryfalse. esplit. splits.
        { rewrite* remove_disjoint_union_l. }
        { applys* Fmap.disjoint_remove_l. }
        { eauto. } } } }
Qed.
The structural rules for evalns asserts that evalns s t Q is covariant in the postcondition Q.
Lemma evalns_conseq : s t Q Q',
  evalns s t Q'
  Q' ===> Q
  evalns s t Q.
Proof using.
  introv M WQ. induction M.
  { applys evalns_val. applys* WQ. }
  { rename H1 into IH.
    applys evalns_step.
    { auto. }
    { introv HR. applys* IH. } }
Qed.
The rules for term constructs are established next. Note that there is no rule stated here for the case of values, because such a rule is already provided by the constructor evalns_val.
Lemma evalns_fix : s f x t1 Q,
  Q (val_fix f x t1) s
  evalns s (trm_fix f x t1) Q.
Proof using.
  introv M. applys evalns_step.
  { do 2 esplit. constructor. }
  { introv R. inverts R. { applys evalns_val. applys M. } }
Qed.

Lemma evalns_app_fix : s f x v1 v2 t1 Q,
  v1 = val_fix f x t1
  evalns s (subst x v2 (subst f v1 t1)) Q
  evalns s (trm_app v1 v2) Q.
Proof using.
  introv E M. applys evalns_step.
  { do 2 esplit. constructors*. }
  { introv R. invert R; try solve [intros; false].
    introv → → → → → R. inverts E. applys M. }
Qed.

Exercise: 5 stars, standard, especially useful (evalns_let)

Prove the big-step reasoning rule for let-bindings for evalns.
Lemma evalns_let : s x t1 t2 Q1 Q,
  evalns s t1 Q1
  ( s1 v1, Q1 v1 s1 evalns s1 (subst x v1 t2) Q)
  evalns s (trm_let x t1 t2) Q.
Proof using. (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Lemma evalns_if : s b t1 t2 Q,
  evalns s (if b then t1 else t2) Q
  evalns s (trm_if b t1 t2) Q.
Proof using.
  introv M. applys evalns_step.
  { do 2 esplit. constructors*. }
  { introv R. inverts R; tryfalse. { applys M. } }
Qed.

Lemma evalns_ref : s v,
  evalns s (val_ref v) (fun r(\ p, \[r = p] \* p ~~> v) \* (= s)).
Proof using.
  intros. applys evalns_step.
  { forwards¬(p&D&N): (exists_fresh null s).
    esplit. (val_loc p). applys* step_ref. }
  { introv R. inverts R; tryfalse. applys evalns_val.
    unfold update. applys¬hstar_intro.
    { p. rewrite¬hstar_hpure_l. split¬. { applys¬hsingle_intro. } }
    { applys* disjoint_single_of_not_indom. } }
Qed.

End EvalnsProperties.

Triples for Small-Step Semantics

The judgment triplens t H Q mimics the definition of hoaren, which was used for defining triples with respect to the big-step judgment evaln.
Definition triplens (t:trm) (H:hprop) (Q:valhprop) : Prop :=
   (s:state), H s evalns s t Q.
From evalns_frame, we can derive the standard frame rule for triplens, exactly like we did in the lemma triplen_frame.
Lemma triplens_frame : t H Q H',
  triplens t H Q
  triplens t (H \* H') (Q \*+ H').
Proof.
  introv M. intros h HF. lets (h1&h2&M1&M2&MD&MU): hstar_inv (rm HF).
  subst. specializes M M1. applys evalns_conseq.
  { applys evalns_frame M MD. } { xsimpl. intros h' →. applys M2. }
Qed.

Reasoning Rules for triplens

Let's now prove reasoning rules for the Hoare triples judgment triplens.
The consequence rule exploits the covariance result for evalns.
Lemma triplens_conseq : t H' Q' H Q,
  triplens t H' Q'
  H ==> H'
  Q' ===> Q
  triplens t H Q.
Proof using.
  introv M MH MQ HF. applys evalns_conseq M MQ. applys* MH.
Qed.
The other two structural rules, which operate on the precondition, admit exactly the same proofs as in the previous chapters.
Lemma triplens_hexists : t (A:Type) (J:Ahprop) Q,
  ( x, triplens t (J x) Q)
  triplens t (hexists J) Q.
Proof using. introv M. intros h (x&Hh). applys M Hh. Qed.

Lemma triplens_hpure : t (P:Prop) H Q,
  (P triplens t H Q)
  triplens t (\[P] \* H) Q.
Proof using.
  introv M. intros h (h1&h2&M1&M2&D&U). destruct M1 as (M1&HP).
  lets E: hempty_inv HP. subst. rewrite Fmap.union_empty_l. applys¬M.
Qed.
The reasoning rules for terms follow directly from the reasoning rules established for evalns.
Lemma triplens_val : v H Q,
  H ==> Q v
  triplens (trm_val v) H Q.
Proof using. introv M. intros h K. applys* evalns_val. Qed.

Lemma triplens_fix : f x t1 H Q,
  H ==> Q (val_fix f x t1)
  triplens (trm_fix f x t1) H Q.
Proof using. introv M. intros h K. applys* evalns_fix. Qed.

Lemma triplens_app_fix : v1 v2 f x t1 H Q,
  v1 = val_fix f x t1
  triplens (subst x v2 (subst f v1 t1)) H Q
  triplens (trm_app v1 v2) H Q.
Proof using. introv E M. intros h K. applys* evalns_app_fix. Qed.

Lemma triplens_let : x t1 t2 H Q Q1,
  triplens t1 H Q1
  ( v1, triplens (subst x v1 t2) (Q1 v1) Q)
  triplens (trm_let x t1 t2) H Q.
Proof using.
  introv M1 M2. intros h K. applys* evalns_let.
  { introv K'. applys* M2. }
Qed.

Lemma triplens_if : (b:bool) t1 t2 H Q,
  triplens (if b then t1 else t2) H Q
  triplens (trm_if b t1 t2) H Q.
Proof using. introv M1. intros h K. applys* evalns_if. Qed.
The evaluation rules for primitive operations are proved in a way that is extremely similar to the proofs used for the big-step case, i.e., to the proofs establishing the reasoning rules for hoaren.
Lemma triplens_add : H n1 n2,
  triplens (val_add n1 n2)
    H
    (fun r\[r = val_int (n1 + n2)] \* H).
Proof using.
  intros. intros s K. applys evalns_step.
  { do 2 esplit. constructors*. }
  { introv R. inverts R. applys evalns_val. rewrite¬hstar_hpure_l. }
Qed.

Lemma triplens_rand : n,
  n > 0
  triplens (val_rand n)
    \[]
    (fun r\ n1, \[0 n1 < n] \* \[r = val_int n1]).
Proof using.
  introv N. intros s K. lets ->: hempty_inv K. applys evalns_step.
  { do 2 esplit. applys* step_rand 0. math. }
  { introv R. inverts R; tryfalse.
    applys evalns_val. applys hexists_intro n1. rewrite¬hstar_hpure_l.
    split¬. applys* hpure_intro. }
Qed.

Lemma triplens_ref : H v,
  triplens (val_ref v)
    H
    (fun r(\ p, \[r = val_loc p] \* p ~~> v) \* H).
Proof using.
  intros. intros h K. applys evalns_conseq. applys* evalns_ref.
  { intros r. xpull. intros ? →. xsimpl*. intros ? →. auto. }
Qed.

Lemma triplens_get : H v p,
  triplens (val_get p)
    ((p ~~> v) \* H)
    (fun r\[r = v] \* (p ~~> v) \* H).
Proof using.
  intros. intros s K. destruct K as (s1&s2&P1&P2&D&U).
  lets E1: hsingle_inv P1. subst s s1. applys evalns_step.
  { do 2 esplit. applys* step_get. applys indom_union_l. applys indom_single. }
  { introv R. inverts R; tryfalse. applys evalns_val.
    rewrite¬hstar_hpure_l. split¬.
    { rewrite read_union_l. { rewrite* read_single. } { applys indom_single. } }
    { applys* hstar_intro. } }
Qed.

Lemma triplens_set : H w p v,
  triplens (val_set (val_loc p) v)
    ((p ~~> w) \* H)
    (fun r\[r = val_unit] \* (p ~~> v) \* H).
Proof using.
  intros. intros s K. destruct K as (s1&s2&P1&P2&D&U).
  lets E1: hsingle_inv P1. subst s s1. applys evalns_step.
  { do 2 esplit. applys* step_set. applys indom_union_l. applys indom_single. }
  { introv R. inverts R; tryfalse. applys evalns_val.
    rewrite hstar_hpure_l. split¬.
    { rewrite update_union_l; [| applys indom_single ].
      rewrite update_single. applys¬hstar_intro.
      { applys¬hsingle_intro. }
      { applys* disjoint_single_set. } } }
Qed.

Lemma triplens_free : H p v,
  triplens (val_free (val_loc p))
    ((p ~~> v) \* H)
    (fun r\[r = val_unit] \* H).
Proof using.
  intros. intros s K. destruct K as (s1&s2&P1&P2&D&U).
  lets E1: hsingle_inv P1. subst s s1. applys evalns_step.
  { do 2 esplit. applys* step_free. applys indom_union_l. applys indom_single. }
  { introv R. inverts R; tryfalse. applys evalns_val.
    rewrite hstar_hpure_l. split¬.
    { rewrite remove_union_single_l. { auto. }
      intros N'. applys disjoint_inv_not_indom_both D N'.
      applys indom_single. } }
Qed.

Weakest-Precondition for Small-Step Semantics.

The definition of wpn can be adpated to use evalns instead of evaln.
Definition wpns (t:trm) (Q:valhprop) : hprop :=
  fun sevalns s t Q.
Structural rules
Lemma wpns_frame : t H Q,
  (wpns t Q) \* H ==> wpns t (Q \*+ H).
Proof using.
  intros. unfold wpn. intros h HF.
  lets (h1&h2&M1&M2&MD&MU): hstar_inv (rm HF).
  subst. applys evalns_conseq.
  { applys evalns_frame M1 MD. }
  { xsimpl. intros h' →. applys M2. }
Qed.

Lemma wpns_conseq : t Q1 Q2,
  Q1 ===> Q2
  (wpns t Q1) ==> (wpns t Q2).
Proof using.
  introv W. unfold wpn. intros h K. applys evalns_conseq K W.
Qed.

Lemma wpns_ramified : t Q1 Q2,
  (wpns t Q1) \* (Q1 \−−∗ Q2) ==> (wpns t Q2).
Proof using.
  intros. applys himpl_trans.
  { applys wpns_frame. }
  { applys wpns_conseq. xsimpl. }
Qed.
Rules for term constructs
Section WpnsRules.
Hint Constructors step.

Lemma wpns_val : v Q,
  Q v ==> wpns (trm_val v) Q.
Proof using. unfold wpns. intros. intros h K. applys* evalns_val. Qed.

Lemma wpns_fix : f x t Q,
  Q (val_fix f x t) ==> wpns (trm_fix f x t) Q.
Proof using. unfold wpns. intros. intros h K. applys* evalns_fix. Qed.

Lemma wpns_app_fix : f x v1 v2 t1 Q,
  v1 = val_fix f x t1
  wpns (subst x v2 (subst f v1 t1)) Q ==> wpns (trm_app v1 v2) Q.
Proof using. unfold wpns. intros. intros h K. applys* evalns_app_fix. Qed.

Lemma wpns_let : x t1 t2 Q,
      wpns t1 (fun vwpns (subst x v t2) Q)
  ==> wpns (trm_let x t1 t2) Q.
Proof using. unfold wpns. intros. intros h K. applys* evalns_let. Qed.

Lemma wpns_if : b t1 t2 Q,
  wpns (if b then t1 else t2) Q ==> wpns (trm_if b t1 t2) Q.
Proof using. unfold wpns. intros. intros h K. applys* evalns_if. Qed.
Rules for primitives. We state their specifications following the presentation described near the end of chapter Wand.
(*
Lemma wpns_add : forall Q n1 n2,
  (Q (val_int (n1 + n2))) ==> wpns (val_add (val_int n1) (val_int n2)) Q.
Proof using.
  unfolds wpns. intros. intros h K. applys* evaln_add.
Qed.

Lemma wpns_rand : forall Q n,
  n > 0 ->
      (\forall n1, \0 n1 < n \−∗ Q (val_int n1))
  ==> wpns (val_rand (val_int n)) Q.
Proof using.
  unfolds wpns. introv N. xsimpl. intros h K.
  applys* evaln_rand. intros n1 H1. lets K': hforall_inv K n1.
  rewrite* hwand_hpure_l in K'.
Qed.
TODO:
*)


(* TODO: move *)
Lemma hwand_elim : H1 H2 h,
  (H1 \−∗ H2) h
  ( h1, Fmap.disjoint h h1 H1 h1 H2 (h1 \u h)).
Proof using.
  introv M. lets (R&_): hwand_equiv (=h) H1 H2.
  forwards N: R. { intros ? →. auto. }
  intros h1 Hh1 D. applys N. applys* hstar_intro.
Qed.

Lemma evalns_ref' : Q v s,
  (\ p, p ~~> v \−∗ Q p) s
  evalns s (val_ref v) Q.
Proof using.
  introv K. applys evalns_step.
  { forwards¬(p&D&N): (exists_fresh null s).
    esplit. (val_loc p). applys* step_ref. }
  { introv R. inverts R; tryfalse. applys evalns_val.
    lets: hforall_specialize p K.
    unfold update. applys hwand_elim H.
    { apply disjoint_sym. applys* Fmap.disjoint_single_of_not_indom. }
    { applys hsingle_intro. } }
Qed.

Lemma wpns_ref' : Q v,
  (\ p, (p ~~> v) \−∗ Q (val_loc p)) ==> wpns (val_ref v) Q.
Proof using. unfold wpns. intros. intros h K. applys* evalns_ref'. Qed.

Lemma wpns_ref : Q v,
  (\ p, (p ~~> v) \−∗ Q (val_loc p)) ==> wpns (val_ref v) Q.
Proof using.
  unfolds wpns. intros. intros h K.
  applys evalns_conseq. applys* evalns_ref. xpull.
  intros ? p →. lets: hforall_specialize p K.
  rewrite <- hwand_equiv. intros ? →. auto.
Qed.

(* TODO
Lemma wpns_get : forall v p Q,
  (p ~~> v) \* (p ~~> v \−∗ Q v) ==> wpns (val_get p) Q.
Proof using.
  unfolds wpns. intros. intros h K.
  lets (h1&h2&P1&P2&D&->): hstar_inv (rm K).
  forwards*: hwand_inv h1 P2.
  lets E1: hsingle_inv P1. lets I1: indom_single p v.
  applys evaln_get.
  { applys* Fmap.indom_union_l. subst. applys indom_single. }
  { subst h1. rewrite* Fmap.read_union_l. rewrite* Fmap.read_single. }
Qed.

Lemma wpns_set : forall v w p Q,
  (p ~~> v) \* (p ~~> w \−∗ Q val_unit) ==> wpns (val_set p w) Q.
Proof using.
  unfolds wpns. intros. intros h K.
  lets (h1&h2&P1&P2&D&->): hstar_inv (rm K).
  lets E1: hsingle_inv P1. lets I1: indom_single p v.
  forwards: hwand_inv (single p w) P2.
  { applys hsingle_intro. }
  { subst h1. applys Fmap.disjoint_single_set D. }
    { applys evaln_set.
    { applys* Fmap.indom_union_l. subst. applys indom_single. }
    { subst h1. rewrite* Fmap.update_union_l. rewrite* update_single. } }
Qed.

Lemma wpns_free : forall v p Q,
  (p ~~> v) \* (Q val_unit) ==> wpns (val_free p) Q.
Proof using.
  unfolds wpns. intros. intros h K.
  lets (h1&h2&P1&P2&D&->): hstar_inv (rm K).
  lets E1: hsingle_inv P1. lets I1: indom_single p v.
  applys_eq evaln_free.
  { applys* Fmap.indom_union_l. subst. applys indom_single. }
  { subst h1. rewrite~ Fmap.remove_union_single_l.
    intros Dl. applys* Fmap.disjoint_inv_not_indom_both D Dl. }
Qed.

*)


End WpnsRules.

Equivalence Between Non-Deterministic Small-Step and Big-Step Sem.

We end this chapter with the proof of equivalence between triplens and hoaren, establishing a formal relationship between triples defined with respect to a small-step semantics and those defined with respect to a big-step semantics.
We start by establishing the equivalence between evalns and evaln. We focus first on the direction from evalns to evaln.
We begin with a key lemma: if a configuration (s1,t1) takes a step to (s2,t2), then this first configuration admits the same postconditions as the second configuration.
Lemma evaln_of_step_and_evaln : s1 t1 Q,
  ( s2 t2, step s1 t1 s2 t2)
  ( s2 t2, step s1 t1 s2 t2 evaln s2 t2 Q)
  evaln s1 t1 Q.
Proof using.
  introv (s2&t2&R1) RS. gen Q. induction R1; intros.
  { applys evaln_let (fun v1 s2evaln s2 (subst x v1 t2) Q).
    { applys IHR1. intros s1b t1b Kb.
      forwards M: RS. { applys step_let_ctx Kb. }
      { inverts M as M1 M2. applys evaln_conseq M1. applys M2. } }
    { intros v1 s' K. applys K. } }
  { applys evaln_fix. forwards M: RS. { applys step_fix. }
    { inverts* M. } }
  { applys* evaln_app_fix. forwards M: RS. { applys* step_app_fix. }
    { applys M. } }
  { applys* evaln_if. forwards M: RS. { applys* step_if. } { applys M. } }
  { applys evaln_let (fun v' s'v' = v1 s' = s).
    { applys* evaln_val. }
    { intros ? ? (->&->). forwards M: RS. { applys* step_let. }
      { applys M. } } }
  { applys* evaln_add. forwards M: RS. { applys* step_add. }
    { inverts* M. } }
  { applys* evaln_rand.
    { math. }
    { intros n2 N2. forwards M: RS. { applys* step_rand n2. }
      { inverts* M. } } }
  { applys evaln_ref. intros p' D.
    forwards M: RS p'. { applys* step_ref. } { inverts* M. } }
  { applys* evaln_get. forwards M: RS. { applys* step_get. }
    { inverts* M. } }
  { applys* evaln_set. forwards M: RS. { applys* step_set. }
    { inverts* M. } }
  { applys* evaln_free. forwards M: RS. { applys* step_free. }
    { inverts* M. } }
Qed.
By exploiting the above lemma over all the evals of an execution, we obtain the fact that evalns implies evaln.
Lemma evaln_of_evalns : s t Q,
  evalns s t Q
  evaln s t Q.
Proof using.
  introv M. induction M.
  { applys* evaln_val. }
  { applys* evaln_of_step_and_evaln. }
Qed.
Let's now turn to the second direction, from evaln to evalns. The proof is carried out by induction on the big-step relation.
Lemma evalns_of_evaln : s t Q,
  evaln s t Q
  evalns s t Q.
Proof using.
  introv M. induction M.
  { applys* evalns_val. }
  { applys evalns_step.
    { do 2 esplit. applys step_fix. }
    { introv K. inverts K. applys* evalns_val. } }
  { rename H into E. applys evalns_step.
    { do 2 esplit. applys* step_app_fix. }
    { introv K. invert K; try solve [ intros; false ].
      introv → → → → → R. inverts E. applys IHM. } }
  { rename M into M1, H into M2, IHM into IHM1, H0 into IHM2.
    tests C: ( v1, t1 = trm_val v1).
    { destruct C as (v1&->). applys evalns_step.
      { do 2 esplit. applys* step_let. }
      { introv K. inverts K as K1 K2.
        { inverts K1. }
        { inverts IHM1 as K3 K4.
          { applys* IHM2. }
          { destruct K3 as (?&?&K5). inverts K5. } } } }
    { applys evalns_step.
      { inverts IHM1 as K3 K4.
        { false* C. }
        { destruct K3 as (?&?&K5). do 2 esplit. applys* step_let_ctx. } }
      { introv K. inverts K as K'; [|false* C].
        inverts IHM1 as K5 K6; [false* C|].
        specializes K6 K'. applys* evalns_let. } } }
  { applys evalns_step.
    { do 2 esplit. applys* step_if. }
    { introv K. inverts K. applys IHM. } }
  { applys evalns_step.
    { do 2 esplit. applys* step_add. }
    { introv K. inverts K. applys* evalns_val. } }
  { applys evalns_step.
    { do 2 esplit. applys* step_rand 0. math. }
    { introv K. inverts K; tryfalse. applys* evalns_val. } }
  { applys evalns_step.
    { forwards¬(p&D&N): (exists_fresh null s).
      do 2 esplit. applys* step_ref. }
    { introv K. inverts K; tryfalse. applys* evalns_val. } }
  { applys evalns_step.
    { do 2 esplit. applys* step_get. }
    { introv K. inverts K; tryfalse. applys* evalns_val. } }
  { applys evalns_step.
    { do 2 esplit. applys* step_set. }
    { introv K. inverts K; tryfalse. applys* evalns_val. } }
  { applys evalns_step.
    { do 2 esplit. applys* step_free. }
    { introv K. inverts K; tryfalse. applys* evalns_val. } }
Qed.
Combining the two directions, we obtain the desired equivalence between the big-step and the small-step characterization of total correctness.
Lemma evalns_eq_evalns :
  evalns = evaln.
Proof using.
  extens. intros s t Q. iff M.
  { applys* evaln_of_evalns. }
  { applys* evalns_of_evaln. }
Qed.
As immediate corollary, we obtain the equivalence between the big-step and the small-step characterization of Hoare triples, for the general case of a non-deterministic language.
Lemma phoare_eq_triplens :
  triplens = hoaren.
Proof using. unfold triplens, hoaren. rewrite* evalns_eq_evalns. Qed.

Historical Notes

At a very low-level, one may view a piece of hardware as being totally deterministic: at each tick of the processor's clock, every hardware component makes a transition according to non-ambiguous rules. Yet, complex hardware architectures are not so deterministic. For example, on a multicore hardware, which of two concurrent writes reaches the memory first is, from the perspective of a program, essentially random. At a higher-level, interactions with the outside world, such as user input, can be seen as sources of non-determinism in a program semantics.
Non-deterministic semantics may be harder to reason about than deterministic semantics. To tame that complexity, a semantics may be "determinized" by parameterizing it with a trace of events, each event reflecting one "choice" that was made during the execution. Reasoning about a determinized semantics equipped with traces may, depending on the context, be easier or carry more information than reasoning about a non-deterministic semantics. Reasoning about traces is, however, beyond the scope of this course.
The predicates evaln (big-step) first appeared in the paper entitled Axiomatic Semantics for Compiler Verification, by Steven Schäfer, Sigurd Schneider, and Gert Smolka (CPP'2016). This predicate, as well as evalns (small-step) are exploited in the paper "Integration Verification Across Software and Hardware for a Simple Embedded System" (PLDI'21). The meta- theory of these judgments is described in details in the paper: "Omnisemantics: Smoother Handling of Nondeterminism" (2022) by Arthur Charguéraud, Adam Chlipala, Andres Erbsen, and Samuel Gruetter. http://www.chargueraud.org/research/2022/omnisemantics/omnisemantics.pdf
(* 2022-09-20 16:51 *)